قانون‌گذاری در جمهوری دینی

نوع مقاله : مقاله پژوهشی

نویسندگان

1 استادیار، گروه حقوق عمومی و بین‌الملل، دانشکده حقوق و علوم سیاسی، دانشگاه شیراز، شیراز، ایران.

2 استادیار گروه حقوق عمومی، دانشگاه آزاد اسلامی دماوند، دماوند، ایران.

10.22099/jls.2024.49195.5083

چکیده

در این مقاله تلاش شده است در رویکردی هنجاری ماهیت قانون و امکان قانون‌گذاری در جمهوری دینی مورد ارزیابی قرار گیرد. سؤال اصلی مقاله عبارت است از آن است که با نظر به دانش هرمنوتیک چگونه می‌توان به سنتزی عقلانی از آمیزش جمهوریت و دین در ترکیب جمهوری دینی یاری رساند و امکان قانون‌گذاری را در نظام دینی میسر ساخت؟ و چنانچه این امر میسر شد، قانون در جمهوری دینی چه ویژگی‌هایی خواهد داشت؟ جمع جمهوریت و دینی بودن منوط به برداشت ویژه‌ای از جمهوری و دین است. جمهوریت واجد ویژگی­هایی هم در شکل و هم در محتوا است. ازاین‌رو جمهوریت به رعایت شکل کاسته نمی‌شود. همچنین دینی بودن اگر ناقض آن شکل یا محتوا باشد، قابل‌جمع با جمهوریت نیست. نظر به دانش هرمنوتیک، دینی بودن نیز امری تفسیری است که در تفسیری حداقلی در دیدگاه این مقاله به حوزه ارزش‌های عام بشری محدود می‌شود. در تفسیر حداقلی از دین، حقوق بشر رعایت می‌شود؛ حوزه اخلاق از حوزه حقوق تفکیک می­گردد و جایگاه دین در به رسمیت شناختن ارزش‌های عامی چون عدالت، آزادی و برابری به رسمیت شناخته می­شود. لذا در برداشت مذکور از جمهوری و دین، جمهوریت دینی ممکن می­گردد و قانون‌گذاری بشری در این نظام با نظر به ارزش‌های عام بشری در حیطه‌ای که عقل پذیرفته است، میسر می‌شود. به‌عبارت‌دیگر، قانون‌گذاری بشری امکان وضع قانون را به‌واسطه طرح «ایده اجتهاد» و با تلقی حداقلی از دین ممکن می‌سازد و بدین ترتیب نقش عقل در فرایند قانون‌گذاری به رسمیت شناخته می‌شود. قانون در پرتو این نظام ماهیتی عقلانی دارد که توسط نمایندگان مردم، با هدف برقراری عدالت وضع و تفسیر می‌شود. ازاین‌رو صاحبان قدرت در جمهوری دینی به متولیان دین محصور نمی‌شوند.

کلیدواژه‌ها

موضوعات


عنوان مقاله [English]

Legal Framework in a Religious Republic

نویسندگان [English]

  • Hadi Salehi 1
  • maryam mirsadeghi 2
1 Assistant Professor, Department of Public and International Law, Faculty of Law and Political Science, University of Shiraz, Shiraz, Iran
2 Assistant Prof, Islamic Azad University, Damavand Branch, Damavand, Iran
چکیده [English]

This article seeks to answer the central question of whether legislation is possible in a religious republic and what role law occupies in such a system. In other words, the main question is how, considering the knowledge of hermeneutics, a rational synthesis can be achieved between republicanism and religion within the framework of a religious republic, thereby enabling the possibility of legislation in such a system. The article adopts a normative approach in addressing this question, considering the current political reality of Iran.
The conceptual possibility of a religious republic is only achievable through a specific interpretation of both republicanism and religion. Republicanism, in this context, incorporates elements both in form and content, and is not reducible merely to its formal aspects. This is because republicanism entails substantive values, such as the primacy of social contracts and public consent. Thus, any limitation that undermines these values is unacceptable. For instance, certain substantive constraints on constitutional amendments or the existence of lifelong and unaccountable institutions violate the principle of republicanism.
Religiosity, in turn, requires a particular interpretation of religion, and only within this specific understanding can it be reconciled with republicanism. In this sense, religiosity is interpretative in nature, as understood through hermeneutics, and is confined to universal human values in a minimal interpretation. In this minimalistic view of religion, human rights are respected, ethics is distinguished from law, and religion is acknowledged as a source of universal values such as justice, freedom, and equality. By adhering to these principles, it becomes possible to reconcile republicanism and religiosity.
In this interpretation of religion, it is considered a subject of interpretation, and no interpretation is deemed sacred. Therefore, the possibility of critique, dialogue, and the clash of ideas regarding interpretations of religion is always present, and no individual can sanctify their interpretation. Additionally, following the philosophical shift in hermeneutics initiated by Heidegger, which extended hermeneutics from mere textual interpretation to human existence—suggesting that our being is inherently interpretive—existential hermeneutics emerged. As a result, human beings are inherently interpretive and constantly engaged in the act of interpretation. Thus, the role of the interpreter cannot be ignored, and this facilitates tolerance among diverse interpretations.
In this unique perspective on religion, expectations of religion are minimal. Religiosity is reduced to adherence to universal values shared among all religions and scholars, such as freedom, equality, and justice. However, the methods for achieving these values are entrusted to modern sciences and expertise, and rigidity in methods under the guise of religiosity is unacceptable. Therefore, a religious republic does not mean a government ruled by religious authorities. Since religiosity is merely about emphasizing universal human values, it does not violate public rights and freedoms and recognizes “having rights.” The excuse of “truth” cannot justify the violation of rights belonging to different moral perspectives.
More precisely, a religious republic places rights in a domain “outside of morality,” since morality is confined to universal human values championed by religions.
In the third section of this article, considering the concept of a religious republic based on the aforementioned interpretation of religion, the law undergoes transformation in four dimensions: “the basis of the law,” “the purpose of the law,” “the authority of the law,” and “the interpretation of the law.” This transformation highlights the distinction between a religious republic and both sacred and secular political systems.
The basis of the law is established through reliance on reason as the foundation of legislation, emphasizing rational principles. The purpose of the law is defined, in a non-jurisprudential sense of religion, as creating a free environment to achieve justice. Similar to modern legal systems, the purpose of legislation in a religious republic is to regulate human relations in order to ensure freedom, equality, human rights, human dignity, and, most notably, justice. These values, which transcend religion, are realized through methods that are not fixed or sacred. Methods in a religious republic are contextual and temporal, meaning they may be effective at one time and ineffective at another.
The authority of the law, under a minimal interpretation of religion, is entrusted not to God but to humans, as human life is constantly changing and evolving. Managing the complexities of daily life requires continuous engagement with the realities of individual and collective human existence. Therefore, this responsibility must be undertaken by a conscious entity capable of maintaining a two-way relationship with these realities. As such, the entire society, through its representatives, is deemed the legitimate authority for legislation. In this framework, religiosity is not a condition for representatives, as the domain of legislation pertains to mutable matters, and the religiosity or irreligiosity of society does not influence the functional content of governance.
The interpretation of the law is not limited to specific individuals but is achieved as a convergent interpretation. This involves merging the horizon of the interpreter—who must inevitably consider realities—with all of their mental assumptions and the text from which they strive to uncover meaning. In other words, human legislation becomes possible through the introduction of the “idea of ijtihad” (independent reasoning) and a minimal interpretation of religion.
Thus, the role of reason in the legislative process is recognized. In this system, the law has a rational nature, with the aim of establishing justice, and it is enacted and interpreted by the people’s representatives. Consequently, the holders of power in a religious republic are not confined to religious authorities.
If the law evolves along these four dimensions in a religious republic, it becomes possible to achieve modern legislation within such a framework. A religious republic will not become an ideological system, will not violate the rights and freedoms of minorities, will recognize the “right to have rights,” and will not condition the enjoyment of rights on adherence to a specific moral system. This transformation enables peaceful coexistence among different moral currents in society. Undoubtedly, in this transformation, the meaning of religion will differ from its traditional interpretation, as previously explained.

کلیدواژه‌ها [English]

  • Religious Republic
  • Interpretation of Religion
  • Values and Methodologies
  • Minimalist Perception of Religion
  • Human Legislation
  • Hermeneutic Knowledge
  • Reason in Legislation
Alavi Tabar, A. (1388). the sovereignty of the people in religious society, in tolerance and management, Tehran, Sarat Publishing. [In Persian]
Alavi Tabar, E. (1382). Religious Intellectuals and Religious Republic, Reflection of Thought, No. 44. [In Persian]
AnNaim, A. (1996). Towards an Islamic Reformation, Syracuse University Press.
Bashiriyah, H., the conflict between religion and democracy, at www.rahesabz.net [In Persian]
Bazargan, M. (1372). The Hereafter and God, the Purpose of the Prophets' Mission, in the 2nd Mission, Collection of Works 17, Tehran, Bazargan Cultural Foundation Publications. [In Persian]
Beheshti, A. (1381). Theoretical Difficulties of Realizing a Religious Republic, Reflection of Thought, No. 28. [In Persian]
Ebadian, M. (1377). Course of the Development of the Concept of the Republic, in Republic and Islamic Revolution, Collection of Articles, Tehran, Organization of Cultural Documents of the Islamic Revolution. [In Persian]
Fakuri, M. (2009). Religious democracy, efficiency and effectiveness, Safir magazine, number 13. [In Persian]
Ghazi, A. (2014).Constitutional Rights and Political Institutions, Tehran, Mizan.
Gronden, J. (2012). Hermeneutics, Tehran, Mahi Publishing. [In Persian]
Haeri Yazdi, M. (1995). Wisdom and Government, London, Shadi Publishing. [In Persian]
Haqiqat, S .On the Proportion of Religion and Democracy., in Religious Democracy, edited by Mohammad Baqer Khorramshad, Volume 1, Tehran, Imam Khomeini Publishing and Editing Institute. [In Persian]
Hashemi, S. (2000). Fundamental Rights of the Islamic Republic of Iran, Volume 1, Tehran: Nashr Dadgstar. [In Persian]
Heydari, Ahmad, Religious democracy in the statement of the supreme leader of the revolution, Journal of Islamic Government, No. 49. [In Persian]
James, W. (1990). Pragmatism, translated by Abdul Karim Rashidian, Tehran, Scientific and Cultural Publishing Company. [In Persian]
Javadi Amoli, A. (1989). Velayat Faqih; Province of Jurisprudence and Justice, Qom, Esra Publishing House. [In Persian]
Kadivar, M., Sharia and Politics, in Religion in the Public Domain, at www.kadivar.com [In Persian]
Kadivar, M. (1996). State theories in Shia jurisprudence, Tehran, Ney publication. [In Persian]
Kadivar, Mohsen, Republic of Religion, at www.Kadivar.com [In Persian]
Kariman Majd, S. (1980). Religious democracy in the framework of liberal democracy, in Dynamic Culture, No. 2, based on the speech of the Supreme Leader on 10/13/79. [In Persian]
Katouzian, N. (1981). An Introduction to the Islamic Republic in a passage on the Iranian Revolution, Tehran, Tehran University Press. [In Persian]
Khosropanah, A. (2013). The Paradox of Islam and Democracy, in the abstract of papers of the International Conference on Religion and Democracy, Ferdowsi University of Mashhad. [In Persian]
Klosko, G. (1389). The history of political philosophy of the classical era, translated by Khashayar Dehimi, Tehran, Ney publication. [In Persian]
Laughlin, M. (2008). Basics of Public Law, translated by Mohammad Rasakh, Tehran, Ney Publishing. [In Persian]
Michel, H. (2007).Thinking about Renewal in Islam, Towards a History of Islamic Ideas on Modernization and Secularization, Utrecht University, in Www. Ssrn.com [In English]
Mir Mohammad Sadeghi, M.(2022). Religion in the Light of Hermeneutics and Existentialism, in the First National Conference of Human Sciences and Islamic Wisdom, at https://civilica.com/doc/1381501 [In Persian]
Mirahamdi, M. (1388). Theory of Religious Republic, Tehran, Shahid Beheshti University Press. [In Persian]
Mirahmadi, M.(2004). Theory of the purposes of the Shariah in Sunni political jurisprudence, Farhang Andisheh, fourth year, number 13. [In Persian]
Mirmousavi, S.(2012). Islam, the tradition of the modern state, Tehran, Ney Publishing. [In Persian]
Mohammadi Gorgani, M. (2017). The Existence of Holy Text, Tehran, Ney Publishing. [In Persian]
Mojtahad Shabastri, M.(2010). What is religious democracy?, Reflection of Thought, No. 19. [In Persian]
Mojtahad Shabestri, M. (2008) Religious Republic from Which Angle, Reflection of Thought, No. 27. [In Persian]
Montesquieu, (2007). The Spirit of Laws, Encyclopædia Britannica. [In English]
Motahari, M. (1990). Around the Islamic Revolution, Tehran, Sadra Publications. [In Persian]
Motahari, M. (1370). Twenty words, Tehran, Sadra Publications. [In Persian]
Motmani Tabatabai, M.(1386). Fundamental Rights, Tehran, Mizan Publishing House. [In Persian]
Mujtahad Shabastri, M.(2008). a critique on the official reading of religion, Tehran, New Design Publications. [In Persian]
Mujtahad Shabestri, M. (1375). Hermeneutics, Books and Traditions, Tehran, Tarh e no Publications. [In Persian]
Naini, M.(1389). Tanbiyeh al-Uma and Tanziyeh al-Mulleh, in an introduction to the awakening of the people, Tehran, Samadiyeh Publications. [In Persian]
Palmer, R. (2018). Science of Hermeneutics, translated by Mohammad Saeed Hanai Kashani, Tehran, Hermes Publishing. [In Persian]
Paydar, H. (2008). The Paradox of Islam and Democracy, in Tolerance and Management, Tehran, Serat Publishing. [In Persian]
Poorfard, M. (1384). Republic of Religion, Qom, Research Institute of Islamic Sciences and Culture. [In Persian]
Qadri, H. (1390). Political Thoughts in the 20th Century, first edition, 1379, Tehran, Samt Publications. [In Persian]
Rasakh, M. (1384). The Theoretical Foundation for Reforming the Legislative System, Tehran, Islamic Council Research Center. [In Persian]
Rasakh, M. (2012). Modernity and Religious Rights, in Haq and Expediency 2, Tehran, Ney Publishing. [In Persian]
Rawls, J. (1999). A Theory of Justice, Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. [In English]
Sherratt, Y. (2007). Philosophy of Continental Social Sciences, translated by Hadi Jalili, Tehran, Ney Publishing. [In Persian]
Soroush, A. (1376). Tolerance and Management, Tehran, Serat. [In Persian]
Soroush, A. (1379). Shari'a Theory Bill and Expansion, Tehran, Sarat Publications. [In Persian]
Soroush, A. (1381). Ehlak Khodayan, Tehran, Tarhe no Publications. [In Persian]
Soroush, A. (1388). Religiosity and Shahriari ritual, in Shahriari ritual and religiosity, policy book 2, Tehran,Serat Publications. [In Persian]
Soroush, A. (1388). Shahriari order and religion, Tehran, Serat Publications. [In Persian]
Soroush, A. (1388). tolerance and management of believers, a speech on the relationship between religion and democracy, in tolerance and management, Tehran, Serat Publishing. [In Persian]
Soroush, A. (2008). analysis of the concept of religious government, in tolerance and management, Tehran, Sarat Publishing. [In Persian]
Soroush, A. (2008). Ideology and worldly religion, in tolerance and management, Tehran, Serat Publishing. [In Persian]
Tajik, M. (2006).Religious Democracy Towards a Dominant Discourse, in Religious Democracy, by Mohammad Bagher Khorramshad, Volume 1, Tehran, Imam Khomeini Adjustment and Publishing Institute. [In Persian]
Ziba Kalam, S. (2010). From democracy to religious democracy, Tehran, Roozbeh Publishing. [In Persian]